Moral Luck and Messy Ethics: An Argument against Moral Realism
Consider moral luck: One of the fundamental principles of morality that we all take for granted in our ordinary moral practice is that factors completely outside of our control should not be relevant to our moral standing. People cannot be assessed for what is not their fault and is instead just a matter of pure luck (Call this the 'control principle'). And, indeed, this moral judgement is clearly reflected in our criminal justice system: we treat murder worse than attempted murder, which is worth than manslaughter, etc. Yet, the problem is that if we were to consistently apply this principle across normal ethical judgements that we make, it would completely erode our ordinary judgements about morality. This was famously pointed out in an essay by Thomas Nagel, and I will just summarize some of the examples of moral luck that he gives.
First, consider resultant luck. Often, we are judged for the way things turn out. For instance, consider someone who drives recklessly and then hits and kills a child, or someone who forgets to check his car break and then hits and kills a child because they cannot break on the road. Someone in this scenario would feel immense guilt and blame themselves for their negligence. Yet, imagine the same scenarios yet in which the person's negligence went unchecked: though they drove recklessly, no one was killed, and though they forgot to check their breaks on time, no one was killed. Legally and morally we treat this latter person as far less blameworthy, despite the fact that the difference between these cases is purely a matter of luck. Whether a child happens to walk out in front of your car is a factor beyond your control. Thus, the outcome of situations influences people's culpability in ways that are purely the result of luck, in violation of the control principle.
Second, consider circumstantial luck. Often, we are blamed and praised for actions that are the result of circumstances we happen to be subject to via luck. For instance, consider that we took someone living in modern America and put them in Nazi Germany. Such a person would have a much greater opportunity for courage or cowardliness. Imagine that this person, if they had lived in such a time and place, had went on to commit horrible crimes. We clearly do not judge them to be as culpable for this than the people who actually did happen to be in such circumstances. People who happen to be lucky or unlucky enough to face certain moral tests are treated differently than those who never have such an opportunity Yet, the difference between those actually born in Nazi Germany and those who were not is as matter of luck.
Third, consider constitutive luck. The kind of person that you are in character and inclination is something that you are praised and blamed for. For instance, consider that one day you learn that I give much of my salary to charity. You would likely think: ‘Wow, Sebastian is really a good person. He must have a truly empathetic and giving character’. However, now suppose that you learn that though I give to charity, I am actually inherently greedy in disposition. I internally want to keep all my money, and I do not enjoy giving. I only do it by controlling my greedy impulses. You may think that it is praiseworthy that I can overcome my greedy impulses. However, you would likely blame me for being greedy. You might say: “If you secretly hate giving away your money and are greedy, that indicates a vice. You are not giving away the money for genuine reasons. In fact, your character is a fundamentally bad one, you should enjoy giving to charity.” In this case, you would be blaming me from the way I’m constituted. However, there is something strange about your moral evaluation in this case. The reason I attained this inherent greediness is a result of my genes and the teachings of my parents, and that I had these genes and this family environment is a result of luck. If you had gotten those same genes and teachings, you too would have been a greedy person. We do not think you should judge people differently based on factors that are completely outside their control. Yet, the fact that I am constituted to be greedy is outside my control since I did not choose the background forces that determined my character.
One thing someone might want to say in response is that we might expect, or at least not be surprised, that basic folk intuition about morality is deeply counterintuitive on realism, but that sustained reflection about morality and discourse in philosophy leads us to resolve these initially absurd results. Yet, moral luck still infects modern ethical theories and has been criminally underdiscussed in philosophy. Additionally, normative ethics is a completely split field: philosophers are basically divided into thirds about what stance to adopt, there have been no signs of converging ethical consensus.
In this post, the data I focused on was moral luck. This is just one way in which ethics strikes me as a highly messy area. Other data that I might have appealed to is that our moral intuitions about paradigm moral cases diverge drastically in contradictory directions. And, resolving the dispute between which system to erect based on these moral intuitions strikes me a nigh-irresolvable. There are many challenges for the realist to face when it comes to moral messiness.
This argument can also be seen as a way in which arguments from moral progress and moral convergence rely on understated evidence. Though there may be evidence that we are progressing morally as a species, there are still deep paradoxes at the root of our moral thinking that pervade our everyday lives. Whether these will eventually resolved is an empirical matter, one that could be at the heart of future debates in metaethics.
Comments
Post a Comment